Think of a hard choice you'll
face in the near future. It might be between two careers -- artist and
accountant -- or places to live -- the city or the country -- or even between
two people to marry -- you could marry Betty or you could marry Lolita. Or it
might be a choice about whether to have children, to have an ailing parent move
in with you, to raise your child in a religion that your partner lives by but
leaves you cold. Or whether to donate your life's savings to charity.
Chances are, the hard choice
you thought of was something big, something momentous, something that matters
to you. Hard choices seem to be occasions for agonizing, hand-wringing, the
gnashing of teeth. But I think we've misunderstood hard choices and the role
they play in our lives. Understanding hard choices uncovers a hidden power each
of us possesses.
What makes a choice hard is
the way the alternatives relate. In any easy choice, one alternative is better
than the other. In a hard choice, one alternative is better in some ways, the
other alternative is better in other ways, and neither is better than the other
overall. You agonize over whether to stay in your current job in the city or
uproot your life for more challenging work in the country because staying is
better in some ways, moving is better in others, and neither is better than the
other overall.
We shouldn't think that all
hard choices are big. Let's say you're deciding what to have for breakfast. You
could have high fiber bran cereal or a chocolate donut. Suppose what matters in
the choice is tastiness and healthfulness. The cereal is better for you, the
donut tastes way better, but neither is better than the other overall, a hard
choice. Realizing that small choices can also be hard may make big hard choices
seem less intractable. After all, we manage to figure out what to have for
breakfast, so maybe we can figure out whether to stay in the city or uproot for
the new job in the country.
We also shouldn't think that
hard choices are hard because we are stupid. When I graduated from college, I
couldn't decide between two careers, philosophy and law. I really loved
philosophy. There are amazing things you can learn as a philosopher, and all
from the comfort of an armchair. But I came from a modest immigrant family
where my idea of luxury was having a pork tongue and jelly sandwich in my
school lunchbox, so the thought of spending my whole life sitting around in
armchairs just thinking, well, that struck me as the height of extravagance and
frivolity. So I got out my yellow pad, I drew a line down the middle, and I tried
my best to think of the reasons for and against each alternative. I remember
thinking to myself, if only I knew what my life in each career would be like.
If only God or Netflix would send me a DVD of my two possible future careers,
I'd be set. I'd compare them side by side, I'd see that one was better, and the
choice would be easy.
But I got no DVD, and because
I couldn't figure out which was better, I did what many of us do in hard
choices: I took the safest option. Fear of being an unemployed philosopher led
me to become a lawyer, and as I discovered, lawyering didn't quite fit. It
wasn't who I was. So now I'm a philosopher, and I study hard choices, and I can
tell you that fear of the unknown, while a common motivational default in
dealing with hard choices, rests on a misconception of them. It's a mistake to
think that in hard choices, one alternative really is better than the other,
but we're too stupid to know which, and since we don't know which, we might as
well take the least risky option. Even taking two alternatives side by side
with full information, a choice can still be hard. Hard choices are hard not
because of us or our ignorance; they're hard because there is no best option.
Now, if there's no best
option, if the scales don't tip in favor of one alternative over another, then
surely the alternatives must be equally good. So maybe the right thing to say
in hard choices is that they're between equally good options. That can't be
right. If alternatives are equally good, you should just flip a coin between
them, and it seems a mistake to think, here's how you should decide between
careers, places to live, people to marry: Flip a coin.
There's another reason for
thinking that hard choices aren't choices between equally good options. Suppose
you have a choice between two jobs: you could be an investment banker or a
graphic artist. There are a variety of things that matter in such a choice,
like the excitement of the work, achieving financial security, having time to
raise a family, and so on. Maybe the artist's career puts you on the cutting
edge of new forms of pictorial expression. Maybe the banking career puts you on
the cutting edge of new forms of financial manipulation. Imagine the two jobs
however you like so that neither is better than the other.
Now suppose we improve one of
them a bit. Suppose the bank, wooing you, adds 500 dollars a month to your
salary. Does the extra money now make the banking job better than the artist
one? Not necessarily. A higher salary makes the banking job better than it was
before, but it might not be enough to make being a banker better than being an
artist. But if an improvement in one of the jobs doesn't make it better than
the other, then the two original jobs could not have been equally good. If you
start with two things that are equally good, and you improve one of them, it
now must be better than the other. That's not the case with options in hard
choices.
So now we've got a puzzle.
We've got two jobs. Neither is better than the other, nor are they equally good.
So how are we supposed to choose? Something seems to have gone wrong here.
Maybe the choice itself is problematic and comparison is impossible. But that
can't be right. It's not like we're trying to choose between two things that
can't be compared. We're weighing the merits of two jobs, after all, not the
merits of the number nine and a plate of fried eggs. A comparison of the
overall merits of two jobs is something we can make, and one we often do make.
I think the puzzle arises
because of an unreflective assumption we make about value. We unwittingly
assume that values like justice, beauty, kindness, are akin to scientific
quantities, like length, mass and weight. Take any comparative question not
involving value, such as which of two suitcases is heavier. There are only
three possibilities. The weight of one is greater, lesser or equal to the
weight of the other. Properties like weight can be represented by real numbers
-- one, two, three and so on -- and there are only three possible comparisons
between any two real numbers. One number is greater, lesser, or equal to the
other. Not so with values. As post-Enlightenment creatures, we tend to assume
that scientific thinking holds the key to everything of importance in our
world, but the world of value is different from the world of science. The stuff
of the one world can be quantified by real numbers. The stuff of the other
world can't. We shouldn't assume that the world of is, of lengths and weights,
has the same structure as the world of ought, of what we should do.
So if what matters to us -- a
child's delight, the love you have for your partner — can't be represented by
real numbers, then there's no reason to believe that in choice, there are only
three possibilities -- that one alternative is better, worse or equal to the
other. We need to introduce a new, fourth relation beyond being better, worse
or equal, that describes what's going on in hard choices. I like to say that
the alternatives are "on a par." When alternatives are on a par, it
may matter very much which you choose, but one alternative isn't better than
the other. Rather, the alternatives are in the same neighborhood of value, in
the same league of value, while at the same time being very different in kind
of value. That's why the choice is hard.
Understanding hard choices in
this way uncovers something about ourselves we didn't know. Each of us has the
power to create reasons. Imagine a world in which every choice you face is an
easy choice, that is, there's always a best alternative. If there's a best
alternative, then that's the one you should choose, because part of being
rational is doing the better thing rather than the worse thing, choosing what
you have most reason to choose. In such a world, we'd have most reason to wear
black socks instead of pink socks, to eat cereal instead of donuts, to live in
the city rather than the country, to marry Betty instead of Lolita. A world
full of only easy choices would enslave us to reasons. When you think about it,
it's nuts to believe that the reasons given to you dictated that you had most
reason to pursue the exact hobbies you do, to live in the exact house you do,
to work at the exact job you do. Instead, you faced alternatives that were on a
par, hard choices, and you made reasons for yourself to choose that hobby, that
house and that job. When alternatives are on a par, the reasons given to us,
the ones that determine whether we're making a mistake, are silent as to what
to do. It's here, in the space of hard choices, that we get to exercise our
normative power, the power to create reasons for yourself, to make yourself
into the kind of person for whom country living is preferable to the urban
life.
When we choose between
options that are on a par, we can do something really rather remarkable. We can
put our very selves behind an option. Here's where I stand. Here's who I am. I
am for banking. I am for chocolate donuts. This response in hard choices is a
rational response, but it's not dictated by reasons given to us. Rather, it's
supported by reasons created by us. When we create reasons for ourselves to
become this kind of person rather than that, we wholeheartedly become the
people that we are. You might say that we become the authors of our own lives.
So when we face hard choices,
we shouldn't beat our head against a wall trying to figure out which
alternative is better. There is no best alternative. Instead of looking for
reasons out there, we should be looking for reasons in here: Who am I to be?
You might decide to be a pink sock-wearing, cereal-loving, country-living
banker, and I might decide to be a black sock-wearing, urban, donut-loving
artist. What we do in hard choices is very much up to each of us.
Now, people who don't
exercise their normative powers in hard choices are drifters. We all know
people like that. I drifted into being a lawyer. I didn't put my agency behind
lawyering. I wasn't for lawyering. Drifters allow the world to write the story
of their lives. They let mechanisms of reward and punishment -- pats on the head,
fear, the easiness of an option — to determine what they do. So the lesson of
hard choices reflect on what you can put your agency behind, on what you can be
for, and through hard choices, become that person.
Far
from being sources of agony and dread, hard choices are precious opportunities
for us to celebrate what is special about the human condition, that the reasons
that govern our choices as correct or incorrect sometimes run out, and it is
here, in the space of hard choices, that we have the power to create reasons
for ourselves to become the distinctive people that we are. And that's why hard
choices are not a curse but a godsend.
Read, Learn and Flourish!
Grow, glow and be great!